We'll begin today's discussion with questions and comments about the topics you've proposed for your second essays. We'll have everyone read their proposals and then ask the group for the sort of feedback they think they most want and need. Final versions of the papers are due by the end of the day on Friday, November 14th.
What is Democracy, what is the Internet and what is Deborah Johnson Talking about?
We'll begin by talking about Sunstein's conclusions and his inspiration for suggesting ways to shape virtual space in the service of democracy. We'll brainstorm about (technical) ways the Web could be augmented to facilitate and promote democratic deliberation without robbing individuals of liberties we consider fundamental. We'll then turn to Johnson's chapter in Internet Ethics about the Internet and Democratic Values. (BTW, what's wrong with the writing style in these notes so far?)
Distinctions Between Politics and Ethics
I don't imagine we'll have a great amount of time to discuss the distinctions between politics and ethics today, I hope you'll read and consider this section in preparation for our discussions next week. Although all political matters might be described as matters of ethics, the modern distinction between the realm of politics and that of ethics is due to Aristotle. Whereas ethics is concerned how one should answer (and justify answers to) the question: "What should I do?", politics is concerned with answers and justifications motivated by questions about how government(s) should be organized and how societies ought to function. At the start of Politics (350 BC), Aristotle wrote:
Every State is a community of some kind, and every community is established with a view to some good; for mankind always act in order to obtain that which they think good. But, if all communities aim at some good, the state or political community, which is the highest of all, and which embraces all the rest, aims at good in a greater degree than any other, and at the highest good.Some people think that the qualifications of a statesman, king, householder, and master are the same, and that they differ, not in kind, but only in the number of their subjects. For example, the ruler over a few is called a master; over more, the manager of a household; over a still larger number, a statesman or king, as if there were no difference between a great household and a small state. The distinction which is made between the king and the statesman is as follows: When the government is personal, the ruler is a king; when, according to the rules of the political science, the citizens rule and are ruled in turn, then he is called a statesman.
But all this is a mistake; for governments differ in kind, as will be evident to any one who considers the matter according to the method which has hitherto guided us. As in other departments of science, so in politics, the compound should always be resolved into the simple elements or least parts of the whole. We must therefore look at the elements of which the state is composed, in order that we may see in what the different kinds of rule differ from one another, and whether any scientific result can be attained about each one of them.
Some questions we might consider at the start of today's discussion:
That to compel a man to furnish contributions of money for the propagation of opinions which he disbelieves and abhors, is sinful and tyrannical; that even the forcing him to support this or that teachers of his own religious persuasion, is depriving him of the comfortable liberty of giving his contributions to the particular pastor whose morals he would make his pattern, and whose powers he feels most persuasive to righteousness; and is withdrawing from the ministry those temporary rewards, which proceeding from an approbation of their personal conduct, are an additional incitement to earnest and unremitting labours for the instruction of mankind; that our civil rights have no dependence on our religious opinions, any more than our opinions in physis or geometry; that therefore the proscribing any citizen as unworthy the public confidence by laying upon him an incapacity of being called to offices of trust and emolument, unless he profess or renounce this or that religious opinion, is depriving him injuriously of those privileges and advantages to which, in common with his fellow citizens, he has a natural right; that it tends also to corrupt the principles of that very religion it is meant to encourage, by bribing, with a monopoly of worldly honours and emoluments, those who will externally profess and conform to it; that though indeed these are criminal who do not withstand such temptation, yet neither are those innocent who lay the bait in their way; that the opinions of men are not the object of civil government, nor under its jurisdiction; that to suffer the civil magistrate to intrude his powers into the field of opinion and to restrain the profession or propagation of principles on supposition of their ill tendency is a dangerous falacy, which at once destroys all religious liberty, because he being of course judge of that tendency will make his opinions the rule of judgment, and approve or condemn the sentiments of others only as they shall square with or differ from his own; that it is time enough for the rightful purposes of civil government for its officers to interfere when principles break out into overt acts against peace and good order; and finally, that truth is great and will prevail if left to herself; that she is the proper and sufficient antagonist to error, and has nothing to fear from the conflict unless by human interposition disarmed of her natural weapons, free argument and debate; errors ceasing to be dangerous when it is permitted freely to contradict them. (from "A Bill for Establishing Religious Freedom," January 19, 1786)
For Tuesday:: Read chapters 1-3 of Duncan Langford's Internet Ethics. If you want me to read a draft of your second paper, please give it to me no later than Tuesday.